home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- No. 90-7675
- --------
- R. A. V., PETITIONER v. CITY OF
- ST. PAUL, MINNESOTA
- on writ of certiorari to the supreme court of
- minnesota
- [June 22, 1992]
-
- Justice Stevens, with whom Justice White and
- Justice Blackmun join as to Part I, concurring in the judg-
- ment.
- Conduct that creates special risks or causes special harms
- may be prohibited by special rules. Lighting a fire near an
- ammunition dump or a gasoline storage tank is especially
- dangerous; such behavior may be punished more severely
- than burning trash in a vacant lot. Threatening someone
- because of her race or religious beliefs may cause particu-
- larly severe trauma or touch off a riot, and threatening a
- high public official may cause substantial social disruption;
- such threats may be punished more severely than threats
- against someone based on, say, his support of a particular
- athletic team. There are legitimate, reasonable, and
- neutral justifications for such special rules.
- This case involves the constitutionality of one such
- ordinance. Because the regulated conduct has some
- communicative content-a message of racial, religious or
- gender hostility-the ordinance raises two quite different
- First Amendment questions. Is the ordinance -overbroad-
- because it prohibits too much speech? If not, is it
- -underbroad- because it does not prohibit enough speech?
- In answering these questions, my colleagues today
- wrestle with two broad principles: first, that certain
- -categories of expression [including `fighting words'] are `not
- within the area of constitutionally protected speech,'- ante,
- at 5 (White, J., concurring in judgment); and second, that
- -[c]ontent-based regulations [of expression] are presump-
- tively invalid.- Ante, at 4 (Opinion of the Court). Although
- in past opinions the Court has repeated both of these
- maxims, it has-quite rightly-adhered to neither with the
- absolutism suggested by my colleagues. Thus, while I agree
- that the St. Paul ordinance is unconstitutionally overbroad
- for the reasons stated in Part II of Justice White's opinion,
- I write separately to suggest how the allure of absolute
- principles has skewed the analysis of both the majority and
- concurring opinions.
- I
- Fifty years ago, the Court articulated a categorical
- approach to First Amendment jurisprudence.
- -There are certain well-defined and narrowly limited
- classes of speech, the prevention and punishment of
- which have never been thought to raise any Constitu-
- tional problem. . . . It has been well observed that such
- utterances are no essential part of any exposition of
- ideas, and are of such slight social value as a step to
- truth that any benefit that may be derived from them
- is clearly outweighed by the social interest in order and
- morality.- Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U. S.
- 568, 571-572 (1942).
- We have, as Justice White observes, often described such
- categories of expression as -not within the area of constitu-
- tionally protected speech.- Roth v. United States, 354 U. S.
- 476, 483 (1957).
- The Court today revises this categorical approach. It is
- not, the Court rules, that certain -categories- of expression
- are -unprotected,- but rather that certain -elements- of
- expression are wholly -proscribable.- To the Court, an
- expressive act, like a chemical compound, consists of more
- than one element. Although the act may be regulated
- because it contains a proscribable element, it may not be
- regulated on the basis of another (nonproscribable) element
- it also contains. Thus, obscene antigovernment speech may
- be regulated because it is obscene, but not because it is
- antigovernment. Ante, at 6. It is this revision of the
- categorical approach that allows the Court to assume that
- the St. Paul ordinance proscribes only fighting words, while
- at the same time concluding that the ordinance is invalid
- because it imposes a content-based regulation on expressive
- activity.
- As an initial matter, the Court's revision of the categori-
- cal approach seems to me something of an adventure in a
- doctrinal wonderland, for the concept of -obscene anti-
- government- speech is fantastical. The category of the
- obscene is very narrow; to be obscene, expression must be
- found by the trier of fact to -appea[l] to the prurient
- interest, . . . depic[t] or describ[e], in a patently offensive
- way, sexual conduct, [and] taken as a whole, lac[k] serious
- literary, artistic, political or scientific value.- Miller v.
- California, 413 U. S. 15, 24 (1973) (emphasis added).
- -Obscene antigovernment- speech, then, is a contradiction
- in terms: If expression is antigovernment, it does not -lac[k]
- serious . . . political . . . value- and cannot be obscene.
- The Court attempts to bolster its argument by likening
- its novel analysis to that applied to restrictions on the time,
- place, or manner of expression or on expressive conduct. It
- is true that loud speech in favor of the Republican Party
- can be regulated because it is loud, but not because it is
- pro-Republican; and it is true that the public burning of the
- American flag can be regulated because it involves public
- burning and not because it involves the flag. But these
- analogies are inapposite. In each of these examples, the
- two elements (e.g., loudness and pro-Republican orienta-
- tion) can coexist; in the case of -obscene antigovernment-
- speech, however, the presence of one element (-obscenity-)
- by definition means the absence of the other. To my mind,
- it is unwise and unsound to craft a new doctrine based on
- such highly speculative hypotheticals.
- I am, however, even more troubled by the second step of
- the Court's analysis-namely, its conclusion that the St.
- Paul ordinance is an unconstitutional content-based
- regulation of speech. Drawing on broadly worded dicta, the
- Court establishes a near-absolute ban on content-based
- regulations of expression and holds that the First Amend-
- ment prohibits the regulation of fighting words by subject
- matter. Thus, while the Court rejects the -all-or-nothing-at-
- all- nature of the categorical approach, ante, at 6, it
- promptly embraces an absolutism of its own: within a
- particular -proscribable- category of expression, the Court
- holds, a government must either proscribe all speech or no
- speech at all. This aspect of the Court's ruling fundamen-
- tally misunderstands the role and constitutional status of
- content-based regulations on speech, conflicts with the very
- nature of First Amendment jurisprudence, and disrupts
- well-settled principles of First Amendment law.
- Although the Court has, on occasion, declared that
- content-based regulations of speech are -never permitted,-
- Police Dept. of Chicago v. Mosley, 408 U. S. 92, 99 (1972),
- such claims are overstated. Indeed, in Mosley itself, the
- Court indicated that Chicago's selective proscription of
- nonlabor picketing was not per se unconstitutional, but
- rather could be upheld if the City demonstrated that
- nonlabor picketing was -clearly more disruptive than [labor]
- picketing.- Id., at 100. Contrary to the broad dicta in
- Mosley and elsewhere, our decisions demonstrate that
- content-based distinctions, far from being presumptively
- invalid, are an inevitable and indispensable aspect of a
- coherent understanding of the First Amendment.
- This is true at every level of First Amendment law. In
- broadest terms, our entire First Amendment jurisprudence
- creates a regime based on the content of speech. The scope
- of the First Amendment is determined by the content of
- expressive activity: Although the First Amendment broadly
- protects -speech,- it does not protect the right to -fix prices,
- breach contracts, make false warranties, place bets with
- bookies, threaten, [or] extort.- Schauer, Categories and the
- First Amendment: A Play in Three Acts, 34 Vand. L. Rev.
- 265, 270 (1981). Whether an agreement among competitors
- is a violation of the Sherman Act or protected activity under
- the Noerr-Pennington doctrine hinges upon the content of
- the agreement. Similarly, -the line between permissible
- advocacy and impermissible incitation to crime or violence
- depends, not merely on the setting in which the speech
- occurs, but also on exactly what the speaker had to say.-
- Young v. American Mini Theatres, Inc., 427 U. S. 50, 66
- (1976) (plurality opinion); see also Musser v. Utah, 333
- U. S. 95, 100-103 (1948) (Rutledge, J., dissenting).
- Likewise, whether speech falls within one of the catego-
- ries of -unprotected- or -proscribable- expression is deter-
- mined, in part, by its content. Whether a magazine is
- obscene, a gesture a fighting word, or a photograph child
- pornography is determined, in part, by its content. Even
- within categories of protected expression, the First Amend-
- ment status of speech is fixed by its content. New York
- Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376 U. S. 254 (1964), and Dun &
- Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders, Inc., 472 U. S. 749
- (1985), establish that the level of protection given to speech
- depends upon its subject matter: speech about public
- officials or matters of public concern receives greater
- protection than speech about other topics. It can, therefore,
- scarcely be said that the regulation of expressive activity
- cannot be predicated on its content: much of our First
- Amendment jurisprudence is premised on the assumption
- that content makes a difference.
- Consistent with this general premise, we have frequently
- upheld content-based regulations of speech. For example,
- in Young v. American Mini Theatres, the Court upheld
- zoning ordinances that regulated movie theaters based on
- the content of the films shown. In FCC v. Pacifica Founda-
- tion, 438 U. S. 726 (1978) (plurality opinion), we upheld a
- restriction on the broadcast of specific indecent words. In
- Lehman v. City of Shaker Heights, 418 U. S. 298 (1974)
- (plurality opinion), we upheld a city law that permitted
- commercial advertising, but prohibited political advertising,
- on city buses. In Broadrick v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601
- (1973), we upheld a state law that restricted the speech of
- state employees, but only as concerned partisan political
- matters. We have long recognized the power of the Federal
- Trade Commission to regulate misleading advertising and
- labeling, see, e.g., Jacob Siegel Co. v. FTC, 327 U. S. 608
- (1946), and the National Labor Relations Board's power to
- regulate an employer's election-related speech on the basis
- of its content. See, e.g., NLRB v. Gissel Packing Co., 395
- U. S. 575, 616-618 (1969). It is also beyond question that
- the Government may choose to limit advertisements for
- cigarettes, see 15 U. S. C. 1331-1340, but not for cigars;
- choose to regulate airline advertising, see Morales v. Trans
- World Airlines, 504 U. S. ___ (1992), but not bus advertis-
- ing; or choose to monitor solicitation by lawyers, see
- Ohralik v. Ohio State Bar Assn., 436 U. S. 447 (1978), but
- not by doctors.
- All of these cases involved the selective regulation of
- speech based on content-precisely the sort of regulation
- the Court invalidates today. Such selective regulations are
- unavoidably content based, but they are not, in my opinion,
- -presumptively invalid.- As these many decisions and
- examples demonstrate, the prohibition on content-based
- regulations is not nearly as total as the Mosley dictum
- suggests.
- Disregarding this vast body of case law, the Court today
- goes beyond even the overstatement in Mosley and applies
- the prohibition on content-based regulation to speech that
- the Court had until today considered wholly -unprotected-
- by the First Amendment-namely, fighting words. This
- new absolutism in the prohibition of content-based regula-
- tions severely contorts the fabric of settled First Amend-
- ment law.
- Our First Amendment decisions have created a rough
- hierarchy in the constitutional protection of speech. Core
- political speech occupies the highest, most protected
- position; commercial speech and nonobscene, sexually
- explicit speech are regarded as a sort of second-class
- expression; obscenity and fighting words receive the least
- protection of all. Assuming that the Court is correct that
- this last class of speech is not wholly -unprotected,- it
- certainly does not follow that fighting words and obscenity
- receive the same sort of protection afforded core political
- speech. Yet in ruling that proscribable speech cannot be
- regulated based on subject matter, the Court does just
- that. Perversely, this gives fighting words greater protec-
- tion than is afforded commercial speech. If Congress can
- prohibit false advertising directed at airline passengers
- without also prohibiting false advertising directed at bus
- passengers and if a city can prohibit political advertise-
- ments in its buses while allowing other advertisements, it
- is ironic to hold that a city cannot regulate fighting words
- based on -race, color, creed, religion or gender- while
- leaving unregulated fighting words based on -union
- membership or homosexuality.- Ante, at 13. The Court
- today turns First Amendment law on its head: Communi-
- cation that was once entirely unprotected (and that still can
- be wholly proscribed) is now entitled to greater protection
- than commercial speech-and possibly greater protection
- than core political speech. See Burson v. Freeman, 504
- U. S. ___, ___ (1992).
- Perhaps because the Court recognizes these perversities,
- it quickly offers some ad hoc limitations on its newly
- extended prohibition on content-based regulations. First,
- the Court states that a content-based regulation is valid
- -[w]hen the content discrimination is based upon the very
- reason the entire class of speech. . .is proscribable.- In a
- pivotal passage, the Court writes
- -the Federal Government can criminalize only those
- physical threats that are directed against the Presi-
- dent, see 18 U. S. C. 871-since the reasons why
- threats of violence are outside the First Amendment
- (protecting individuals from the fear of violence, from
- the disruption that fear engenders, and from the
- possibility that the threatened violence will occur) have
- special force when applied to the. . .President.- Ante,
- at 10.
- As I understand this opaque passage, Congress may choose
- from the set of unprotected speech (all threats) to proscribe
- only a subset (threats against the President) because those
- threats are particularly likely to cause -fear of violence,-
- -disruption,- and actual -violence.-
- Precisely this same reasoning, however, compels the
- conclusion that St. Paul's ordinance is constitutional. Just
- as Congress may determine that threats against the
- President entail more severe consequences than other
- threats, so St. Paul's City Council may determine that
- threats based on the target's race, religion, or gender cause
- more severe harm to both the target and to society than
- other threats. This latter judgment-that harms caused by
- racial, religious, and gender-based invective are qualitative-
- ly different from that caused by other fighting
- words-seems to me eminently reasonable and realistic.
- Next, the Court recognizes that a State may regulate
- advertising in one industry but not another because -the
- risk of fraud (one of the characteristics that justifies
- depriving [commercial speech] of full First Amendment
- protection . . .)- in the regulated industry is -greater- than
- in other industries. Ante, at 10. Again, the same reasoning
- demonstrates the constitutionality of St. Paul's ordinance.
- -[O]ne of the characteristics that justifies- the constitutional
- status of fighting words is that such words -by their very
- utterance inflict injury or tend to incite an immediate
- breach of the peace.- Chaplinsky, 315 U. S., at 572.
- Certainly a legislature that may determine that the risk of
- fraud is greater in the legal trade than in the medical trade
- may determine that the risk of injury or breach of peace
- created by race-based threats is greater than that created
- by other threats.
- Similarly, it is impossible to reconcile the Court's analysis
- of the St. Paul ordinance with its recognition that ``a
- prohibition of fighting words that are directed at certain
- persons or groups . . . would be facially valid.'' Ante, at 13
- (emphasis deleted). A selective proscription of unprotected
- expression designed to protect ``certain persons or groups''
- (for example, a law proscribing threats directed at the
- elderly) would be constitutional if it were based on a
- legitimate determination that the harm created by the
- regulated expression differs from that created by the
- unregulated expression (that is, if the elderly are more
- severely injured by threats than are the nonelderly). Such
- selective protection is no different from a law prohibiting
- minors (and only minors) from obtaining obscene publica-
- tions. See Ginsberg v. New York, 390 U. S. 629 (1968). St.
- Paul has determined-reasonably in my judgment-that
- fighting-word injuries ``based on race, color, creed, religion
- or gender'' are qualitatively different and more severe than
- fighting-word injuries based on other characteristics.
- Whether the selective proscription of proscribable speech is
- defined by the protected target (-certain persons or groups-)
- or the basis of the harm (injuries -based on race, color,
- creed, religion or gender-) makes no constitutional differ-
- ence: what matters is whether the legislature's selection is
- based on a legitimate, neutral, and reasonable distinction.
- In sum, the central premise of the Court's ruling-that
- -[c]ontent-based regulations are presumptively inval-
- id--has simplistic appeal, but lacks support in our First
- Amendment jurisprudence. To make matters worse, the
- Court today extends this overstated claim to reach catego-
- ries of hitherto unprotected speech and, in doing so, wreaks
- havoc in an area of settled law. Finally, although the Court
- recognizes exceptions to its new principle, those exceptions
- undermine its very conclusion that the St. Paul ordinance
- is unconstitutional. Stated directly, the majority's position
- cannot withstand scrutiny.
- II
- Although I agree with much of Justice White's analysis,
- I do not join Part I-A of his opinion because I have reserva-
- tions about the -categorical approach- to the First Amend-
- ment. These concerns, which I have noted on other
- occasions, see, e.g., New York v. Ferber, 458 U. S. 747, 778
- (1982) (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment), lead me to
- find Justice White's response to the Court's analysis
- unsatisfying.
- Admittedly, the categorical approach to the First Amend-
- ment has some appeal: either expression is protected or it
- is not-the categories create safe harbors for governments
- and speakers alike. But this approach sacrifices subtlety
- for clarity and is, I am convinced, ultimately unsound. As
- an initial matter, the concept of -categories- fits poorly with
- the complex reality of expression. Few dividing lines in
- First Amendment law are straight and unwavering, and
- efforts at categorization inevitably give rise only to fuzzy
- boundaries. Our definitions of ``obscenity,'' see, e.g., Marks
- v. United States, 430 U. S. 188, 198 (1977) (Stevens, J.,
- concurring in part and dissenting in part), and ``public
- forum,'' see, e.g., United States Postal Service v. Council of
- Greenburgh Civic Assns., 453 U. S. 114, 126-131 (1981); id.,
- at 136-140 (Brennan, J., concurring in judgment); id., at
- 147-151 (Marshall, J., dissenting); 152-154 (Stevens, J.,
- dissenting) (all debating the definition of -public forum-),
- illustrate this all too well. The quest for doctrinal certainty
- through the definition of categories and subcategories is, in
- my opinion, destined to fail.
- Moreover, the categorical approach does not take serious-
- ly the importance of context. The meaning of any expres-
- sion and the legitimacy of its regulation can only be
- determined in context. Whether, for example, a picture or
- a sentence is obscene cannot be judged in the abstract, but
- rather only in the context of its setting, its use, and its
- audience. Similarly, although legislatures may freely
- regulate most nonobscene child pornography, such pornog-
- raphy that is part of -a serious work of art, a documentary
- on behavioral problems, or a medical or psychiatric teaching
- device,- may be entitled to constitutional protection; the
- ``question whether a specific act of communication is
- protected by the First Amendment always requires some
- consideration of both its content and its context.'' Ferber,
- 458 U. S. at 778 (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment); see
- also Smith v. United States, 431 U. S. 291, 311-321 (1977)
- (Stevens, J., dissenting). The categorical approach sweeps
- too broadly when it declares that all such expression is
- beyond the protection of the First Amendment.
- Perhaps sensing the limits of such an all-or-nothing
- approach, the Court has applied its analysis less categori-
- cally than its doctrinal statements suggest. The Court has
- recognized intermediate categories of speech (for example,
- for indecent nonobscene speech and commercial speech) and
- geographic categories of speech (public fora, limited public
- fora, nonpublic fora) entitled to varying levels of protection.
- The Court has also stringently delimited the categories of
- unprotected speech. While we once declared that -[l]ibelous
- utterances [are] not . . . within the area of constitutionally
- protected speech, Beauharnais v. Illinois, 343 U. S. 250, 266
- (1952), our rulings in New York Times Co. v. Sullivan, 376
- U. S. 253 (1964); Gertz v. Robert Welch, Inc., 418 U. S. 323
- (1974), and Dun & Bradstreet, Inc. v. Greenmoss Builders,
- Inc., 472 U. S. 749 (1985), have substantially qualified this
- broad claim. Similarly, we have consistently construed the
- -fighting words- exception set forth in Chaplinsky narrowly.
- See, e.g., Houston v. Hill, 482 U. S. 451 (1987); Lewis v.
- City of New Orleans, 415 U. S. 130 (1974); Cohen v.
- California, 403 U. S. 15 (1971). In the case of commercial
- speech, our ruling that -the Constitution imposes no . . .
- restraint on government [regulation] as respects purely
- commercial advertising,- Valentine v. Chrestensen, 316 U. S.
- 52, 54 (1942), was expressly repudiated in Virginia Bd. of
- Pharmacy v. Virginia Citizens Consumer Council, Inc., 425
- U. S. 748 (1976). In short, the history of the categorical
- approach is largely the history of narrowing the categories
- of unprotected speech.
- This evolution, I believe, indicates that the categorical
- approach is unworkable and the quest for absolute catego-
- ries of -protected- and -unprotected- speech ultimately
- futile. My analysis of the faults and limits of this approach
- persuades me that the categorical approach presented in
- Part I-A of Justice White's opinion is not an adequate
- response to the novel -underbreadth- analysis the Court
- sets forth today.
- III
- As the foregoing suggests, I disagree with both the
- Court's and part of Justice White's analysis of the consti-
- tutionality St. Paul ordinance. Unlike the Court, I do not
- believe that all content-based regulations are equally infirm
- and presumptively invalid; unlike Justice White, I do not
- believe that fighting words are wholly unprotected by the
- First Amendment. To the contrary, I believe our decisions
- establish a more complex and subtle analysis, one that
- considers the content and context of the regulated speech,
- and the nature and scope of the restriction on speech.
- Applying this analysis and assuming arguendo (as the
- Court does) that the St. Paul ordinance is not overbroad, I
- conclude that such a selective, subject-matter regulation on
- proscribable speech is constitutional.
- Not all content-based regulations are alike; our decisions
- clearly recognize that some content-based restrictions raise
- more constitutional questions than others. Although the
- Court's analysis of content-based regulations cannot be
- reduced to a simple formula, we have considered a number
- of factors in determining the validity of such regulations.
- First, as suggested above, the scope of protection provided
- expressive activity depends in part upon its content and
- character. We have long recognized that when government
- regulates political speech or -the expression of editorial
- opinion on matters of public importance,- FCC v. League of
- Women Voters of California, 468 U. S. 364, 375-376 (1984),
- -First Amendment protectio[n] is `at its zenith.'- Meyer v.
- Grant, 486 U. S. 414, 425 (1988). In comparison, we have
- recognized that -commercial speech receives a limited form
- of First Amendment protection,- Posadas de Puerto Rico
- Associates v. Tourism Co. of Puerto Rico, 478 U. S. 328, 340
- (1986), and that -society's interest in protecting [sexually
- explicit films] is of a wholly different, and lesser magnitude
- than [its] interest in untrammeled political debate.- Young
- v. American Mini Theatres, 427 U. S., at 70; see also FCC
- v. Pacifica Foundation, 438 U. S. 726 (1978). The character
- of expressive activity also weighs in our consideration of its
- constitutional status. As we have frequently noted, -[t]he
- government generally has a freer hand in restricting
- expressive conduct than it has in restricting the written or
- spoken word.- Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S. 397, 406 (1989);
- see also United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S. 367 (1968).
- The protection afforded expression turns as well on the
- context of the regulated speech. We have noted, for
- example, that -[a]ny assessment of the precise scope of
- employer expression, of course, must be made in the context
- of its labor relations setting . . . [and] must take into
- account the economic dependence of the employees on their
- employers.- NLRB v. Gissel Packing Co., 395 U. S., at 617.
- Similarly, the distinctive character of a university environ-
- ment, see Widmar v. Vincent, 454 U. S. 263, 277-280 (1981)
- (Stevens, J., concurring in judgment), or a secondary school
- environment, see Hazelwood School Dist. v. Kuhlmeier, 484
- U. S. 260 (1988), influences our First Amendment analysis.
- The same is true of the presence of a -`captive audience[,
- one] there as a matter of necessity, not of choice.'- Lehman
- v. City of Shaker Heights, 418 U. S., at 302 (citation
- omitted). Perhaps the most familiar embodiment of the
- relevance of context is our -fora- jurisprudence, differentiat-
- ing the levels of protection afforded speech in different
- locations.
- The nature of a contested restriction of speech also
- informs our evaluation of its constitutionality. Thus, for
- example, -[a]ny system of prior restraints of expression
- comes to this Court bearing a heavy presumption against
- its constitutional validity.- Bantam Books, Inc. v. Sullivan,
- 372 U. S. 58, 70 (1963). More particularly to the matter of
- content-based regulations, we have implicitly distinguished
- between restrictions on expression based on subject matter
- and restrictions based on viewpoint, indicating that the
- latter are particularly pernicious. -If there is a bedrock
- principle underlying the First Amendment, it is that the
- Government may not prohibit the expression of an idea
- simply because society finds the idea itself offensive or
- disagreeable.- Texas v. Johnson, 491 U. S., at 414. -View-
- point discrimination is censorship in its purest form,- Perry
- Education Assn. v. Perry Local Educators' Assn., 460 U. S.
- 37, 62 (1983) (Brennan, J., dissenting), and requires
- particular scrutiny, in part because such regulation often
- indicates a legislative effort to skew public debate on an
- issue. See, e.g., Schacht v. United States, 398 U. S. 58, 63
- (1970). -Especially where . . . the legislature's suppression
- of speech suggests an attempt to give one side of a debat-
- able public question an advantage in expressing its views
- to the people, the First Amendment is plainly offended.-
- First National Bank of Boston v. Bellotti, 435 U. S. 765,
- 785-786 (1978). Thus, although a regulation that on its
- face regulates speech by subject matter may in some
- instances effectively suppress particular viewpoints, see,
- e.g., Consolidated Edison Co. of N.Y. v. Public Service
- Comm'n of N.Y., 447 U. S. 530, 546-547 (1980) (Stevens,
- J., concurring in judgment), in general, viewpoint-based
- restrictions on expression require greater scrutiny than
- subject-matter based restrictions.
- Finally, in considering the validity of content-based
- regulations we have also looked more broadly at the scope
- of the restrictions. For example, in Young v. American Mini
- Theatres, 427 U. S., at 71, we found significant the fact that
- -what [was] ultimately at stake [was] nothing more than a
- limitation on the place where adult films may be exhibited.-
- Similarly, in FCC v. Pacifica Foundation, the Court
- emphasized two dimensions of the limited scope of the FCC
- ruling. First, the ruling concerned only broadcast material
- which presents particular problems because it -confronts
- the citizen . . . in the privacy of the home-; second, the
- ruling was not a complete ban on the use of selected
- offensive words, but rather merely a limitation on the times
- such speech could be broadcast. 438 U. S., at 748-750.
- All of these factors play some role in our evaluation of
- content-based regulations on expression. Such a multi-
- faceted analysis cannot be conflated into two dimensions.
- Whatever the allure of absolute doctrines, it is just too
- simple to declare expression -protected- or -unprotected- or
- to proclaim a regulation -content-based- or -content-
- neutral.-
- In applying this analysis to the St. Paul ordinance, I
- assume arguendo-as the Court does-that the ordinance
- regulates only fighting words and therefore is not over-
- broad. Looking to the content and character of the regulat-
- ed activity, two things are clear. First, by hypothesis the
- ordinance bars only low-value speech, namely, fighting
- words. By definition such expression constitutes -no
- essential part of any exposition of ideas, and [is] of such
- slight social value as a step to truth that any benefit that
- may be derived from [it] is clearly outweighed by the social
- interest in order and morality.'' Chaplinsky, 315 U. S., at
- 572. Second, the ordinance regulates -expressive conduct
- [rather] than . . . the written or spoken word.- Texas v.
- Johnson, 491 U. S., at 406.
- Looking to the context of the regulated activity, it is
- again significant that the statute (by hypothesis) regulates
- only fighting words. Whether words are fighting words is
- determined in part by their context. Fighting words are not
- words that merely cause offense; fighting words must be
- directed at individuals so as to -by their very utterance
- inflict injury.- By hypothesis, then, the St. Paul ordinance
- restricts speech in confrontational and potentially violent
- situations. The case at hand is illustrative. The cross-
- burning in this case-directed as it was to a single African-
- American family trapped in their home-was nothing more
- than a crude form of physical intimidation. That this cross-
- burning sends a message of racial hostility does not
- automatically endow it with complete constitutional
- protection.
- Significantly, the St. Paul ordinance regulates speech not
- on the basis of its subject matter or the viewpoint ex-
- pressed, but rather on the basis of the harm the speech
- causes. In this regard, the Court fundamentally misreads
- the St. Paul ordinance. The Court describes the St. Paul
- ordinance as regulating expression ``addressed to one of
- [several] specified disfavored topics,'' ante, at 13 (emphasis
- supplied), as policing ``disfavored subjects,'' ibid. (emphasis
- supplied), and as ``prohibit[ing] . . . speech solely on the
- basis of the subjects the speech addresses.'' Ante, at 3
- (emphasis supplied). Contrary to the Court's suggestion,
- the ordinance regulates only a subcategory of expression
- that causes injuries based on ``race, color, creed, religion or
- gender,'' not a subcategory that involves discussions that
- concern those characteristics. The ordinance, as construed
- by the Court, criminalizes expression that ``one knows . . .
- [by its very utterance inflicts injury on] others on the basis
- of race, color, creed, religion or gender.'' In this regard, the
- ordinance resembles the child pornography law at issue in
- Ferber, which in effect singled out child pornography
- because those publications caused far greater harms than
- pornography involving adults.
- Moreover, even if the St. Paul ordinance did regulate
- fighting words based on its subject matter, such a regula-
- tion would, in my opinion, be constitutional. As noted
- above, subject-matter based regulations on commercial
- speech are widespread and largely unproblematic. As we
- have long recognized, subject-matter regulations generally
- do not raise the same concerns of government censorship
- and the distortion of public discourse presented by view-
- point regulations. Thus, in upholding subject-matter
- regulations we have carefully noted that viewpoint-based
- discrimination was not implicated. See Young v. American
- Mini Theatres, 427 U. S., at 67 (emphasizing -the need for
- absolute neutrality by the government,- and observing that
- the contested statute was not animated by -hostility for the
- point of view- of the theatres); FCC v. Pacifica Foundation,
- 438 U. S., at 745-746 (stressing that -government must
- remain neutral in the marketplace of ideas-); see also FCC
- v. League of Women's Voters of California, 468 U. S., at
- 412-417 (Stevens, J., dissenting); Metromedia, Inc. v. City
- of San Diego, 453 U. S. 490, 554-555 (1981) (Stevens, J.,
- dissenting in part). Indeed, some subject-matter restric-
- tions are a functional necessity in contemporary gover-
- nance: -The First Amendment does not require States to
- regulate for problems that do not exist.- Burson v. Free-
- man, 504 U. S. ___, ___ (1992) (slip op., at 16).
- Contrary to the suggestion of the majority, the St. Paul
- ordinance does not regulate expression based on viewpoint.
- The Court contends that the ordinance requires proponents
- of racial intolerance to -follow the Marquis of Queensbury
- Rules- while allowing advocates of racial tolerance to -fight
- freestyle.- The law does no such thing.
- The Court writes:
- -One could hold up a sign saying, for example, that all
- `anti-Catholic bigots' are misbegotten; but not that all
- `papists' are, for that would insult and provoke violence
- `on the basis of religion.'- Ante, at 13.
- This may be true, but it hardly proves the Court's point.
- The Court's reasoning is asymmetrical. The response to a
- sign saying that -all [religious] bigots are misbegotten- is a
- sign saying that -all advocates of religious tolerance are
- misbegotten.- Assuming such signs could be fighting words
- (which seems to me extremely unlikely), neither sign would
- be banned by the ordinance for the attacks were not -based
- on . . . religion- but rather on one's beliefs about tolerance.
- Conversely (and again assuming such signs are fighting
- words), just as the ordinance would prohibit a Muslim from
- hoisting a sign claiming that all Catholics were misbegot-
- ten, so the ordinance would bar a Catholic from hoisting a
- similar sign attacking Muslims.
- The St. Paul ordinance is evenhanded. In a battle
- between advocates of tolerance and advocates of intolerance,
- the ordinance does not prevent either side from hurling
- fighting words at the other on the basis of their conflicting
- ideas, but it does bar both sides from hurling such words on
- the basis of the target's -race, color, creed, religion or
- gender.- To extend the Court's pugilistic metaphor, the St.
- Paul ordinance simply bans punches -below the belt--by
- either party. It does not, therefore, favor one side of any
- debate.
- Finally, it is noteworthy that the St. Paul ordinance is, as
- construed by the Court today, quite narrow. The St. Paul
- ordinance does not ban all -hate speech,- nor does it ban,
- say, all cross-burnings or all swastika displays. Rather it
- only bans a subcategory of the already narrow category of
- fighting words. Such a limited ordinance leaves open and
- protected a vast range of expression on the subjects of
- racial, religious, and gender equality. As construed by the
- Court today, the ordinance certainly does not -`raise the
- specter that the Government may effectively drive certain
- ideas or viewpoints from the marketplace.'- Ante, at 9.
- Petitioner is free to burn a cross to announce a rally or to
- express his views about racial supremacy, he may do so on
- private property or public land, at day or at night, so long
- as the burning is not so threatening and so directed at an
- individual as to -by its very [execution] inflict injury.- Such
- a limited proscription scarcely offends the First Amend-
- ment.
- In sum, the St. Paul ordinance (as construed by the
- Court) regulates expressive activity that is wholly pro-
- scribable and does so not on the basis of viewpoint, but
- rather in recognition of the different harms caused by such
- activity. Taken together, these several considerations
- persuade me that the St. Paul ordinance is not an unconsti-
- tutional content-based regulation of speech. Thus, were the
- ordinance not overbroad, I would vote to uphold it.
-